Abstract: Requiring
a position to meet its burden of proof before it can be believed is a bad
approach to decision-making. In reality, decisions often need to be made before
any proofs can be produced. In this essay, I show what are the flaws of the burden-of-proof logic. I suggest a different way of evaluating
beliefs, which is consistent with necessity of making decisions under
uncertainty. I also address most popular arguments put forward by the
proponents of the burden-of-proof logic. Finally, I try to explain what are the
reasons and consequences of adopting their way of thinking.
Introduction
Burden of proof is a framework of logical thinking used to establish validity of certain claims about reality. It indicates which side should provide arguments for their case. Many atheists argue that theists should provide arguments, because these are theists who make a claim about reality: “God exists.” On the other hand, atheists do not make a claim about reality; they merely reject the theist claim. The default position of a skeptic and a rational person is, according to the burden-of-proof logic, disbelief in a claim until sufficient evidence is provided.
Burden of proof is a framework of logical thinking used to establish validity of certain claims about reality. It indicates which side should provide arguments for their case. Many atheists argue that theists should provide arguments, because these are theists who make a claim about reality: “God exists.” On the other hand, atheists do not make a claim about reality; they merely reject the theist claim. The default position of a skeptic and a rational person is, according to the burden-of-proof logic, disbelief in a claim until sufficient evidence is provided.
A common response to this reasoning is that atheists put forward an
alternative claim: “God does not exist.” But according to many atheists, this is not the
case. The discussion is only about the claim made by theists. For example, a person who has
never learnt the notion of a god is also an atheist. Such a person could never
make a claim one way or the other. Moreover, when rejecting a claim, you are
not making yourself automatically a proponent of an alternative claim. There
are things about the Universe that we just simply do not know yet. You cannot
be forced to automatically accept a bad claim because you rejected another bad
claim. Finally, there are an infinite number of claims that can be made up by a
person with good imagination. It is impossible to even name them, let alone
produce reliable counterevidence to all of them. Therefore, a default position
must be to disbelieve a claim until evidence for it is provided, without being
forced to accept an alternative claim in the meantime. The evidence does not
have to take a tangible form. It can be in form of sound reasoning or even
vague clues in some cases.
Although there are, no doubt, a considerable variety of
opinions on this matter, the above explanation more or less summarizes why many
atheists think that the burden of proof lies with theists. Some theists try to
turn this argument around. They say that atheists are indeed making a claim
that “God does not exist.” Also, there is good evidence for their case and
there is insufficient evidence for the case of atheists, therefore it is atheists’
turn to argue for themselves. However, these arguments do not go deep enough.
In most debates, atheists present much higher level of knowledge and sophistication in their
thinking then their adversaries. Since they have hard time arguing otherwise, it
may seem that theists are indeed the ones who need to provide justification for
their claims and the burden of proof lies with them.
The philosophical questions that are interesting to me are:
is burden of proof a valid framework of logical thinking? Will using it improve
quality of the inferences we make about reality or should we use a different
framework? What different framework would be better? And if burden of proof is
the best framework, how to decide who has the burden of proof? Is there a
general rule or the rule depends on the situation?
In this essay I indent to answer these questions by picking
apart the burden-of-proof logic and by addressing most common arguments supporting
it. But before I start this job, let me briefly explain why it should be
important to both sides of the debate: application of burden of proof shapes
communication between atheists and theists. It generates some confusion and
disagreement. It will be hard to come to an agreement if the parties use different logic, and especially hard if the parties use faulty logic. So,
whatever side you are on, if you care for the truth to prevail, in your
interest is to get both yours and your opponent’s logic straight.
Decisions matter
Why are the debates between theists and atheists important?
Why are debates important in general? The debates I want to discuss in this
essay are a way of exchanging information that is supposed to help establish
what is the nature of reality. You can have such a debate in your own head when
you consider pros and cons of some claims. We can also hold such a debate in
public to educate people and show to the undecided which arguments are
stronger. Regardless of whether argument goes on in your head or in public, the
same logic should govern the reasoning: the correct logic.
Why do we care what the nature of reality is? We care about
it because our vision of reality influences our decisions, which in turn
reflect on our wellbeing. If somebody harbors in his head a belief that bears
no effect on his decision whatsoever, this belief is irrelevant to other people
and to the entire outside world. For some people it may be interesting to
indulge in “academic discussion” about such beliefs, but for the sake of this
argument, I am going to consider only beliefs that influence our decisions.
The theory of
decisions under uncertainty
Consider the following scenario: you are speeding on a
highway. There is a turn ahead. You are wondering whether there are police
waiting behind it. If there are, you are probably going to get a ticket. Now,
you have to decide whether to slow down or maintain your speed.
This is a typical problem in which you have to make a
decision under uncertainty. You have some prior information about the situation
– you have your past experience with police and you have heard many stories.
You also know the approximate costs and benefits of each choice: the
approximate value of the ticket, the amount of time lost by being pulled over and
the amount of time lost by slowing down to avoid the ticket.
So let us apply the burden-of-proof logic to this situation.
The default position is disbelief in the claim that police exists until sufficient
evidence is provided. And since there is no proof that they are there, the
decision should be clearly to keep on speeding. But we know this is a wrong
decision under some circumstances, especially if you know that police really
like to be there. Either the burden-of-proof logic is not working here or I
have misapplied it. You can argue the latter by saying that the claim should be
“there is a 10% chance that police is behind the corner.” Your burden of proof is
now met by your previous experience with cops but you must have arguments both
in favor and against their existence to evaluate the probability.
This is the way we seem to make decisions. We consider
alternative versions of reality – in fact cops either are there or they are
not. We assign a probability value to each version of reality. Then we think
about costs and benefits of our decisions under each version of reality and we
choose the option that is best for us. This is how rational decisions are usually modelled in social sciences.
‘Wait a minute’ you
may think. ‘But many people don’t evaluate probabilities and don’t build a
comprehensive cost-benefit analysis when they make decisions!’
That is correct. Many people do not consider consequences of
their decisions and do not consider how probable their assumptions are. We call
such decisions irrational. In virtually every decision made by humans, there is
a component of irrationality. We do not have enough intellectual capacity to
process all information efficiently. However, we are quite good at
approximating rational decisions even when we do not explicitly think about probabilities.
Moreover, it has been proven over and over again that the more irrationality in
the decision-making process, the worse the results on average. An agent
concerned with her wellbeing must aspire to be as rational as possible.
Therefore, I am going to assume that the decisions we discuss are rational.
Consider a different example: a claim that some diseases are
caused by germs. Belief in such a claim can yield significant benefits. For
example, you can start washing your hands, which can extend your expected life span
by a few years. Today people ascribe a very high probability to this claim. But
a few centuries ago it did not even occur to them. They were acting as if they
assigned zero probability to this claim.
In a rational decision-making process you need to consider
alternative versions of reality and assign them probabilities. The version of
reality that did not occur to you gets by default probability zero. Being
rational means choosing best option given the information you have. Being rational
does not depend on the quality of the information you have. If you have
insufficient or false information, your decision can still be rational if based
solely on this information. People who were not washing their hands were
rational, they just had insufficient information.
Let us go back to the question about a god. First, recall
that we are interested in decisions and their consequences. Going to church can
have different costs and benefits depending on which version of reality is
true: “God exists” or “God does not exist.” A rational person concerned with
her wellbeing should assign probabilities to both claims and choose the best
option. The process of evaluating probabilities requires both arguments against
and arguments in favor of existence of a god. If you had arguments for only one
side, you would end up with probability 1 or 0. If you had no arguments
whatsoever, the probability would be a half for each.
It is impossible to square the burden-of-proof logic with
rational decision making. Evaluating a single claim about the nature of reality
in isolation does not make sense because it cannot well translate into a
decision. In order to have a decision, you need to evaluate at least two claims
and assign them probabilities (keep in mind that probabilities must sum to one).
As a result, it turns out that the burden-of-proof logic is useless.
You can’t prove
negative
After establishing that the logic at its core is flawed, I
need to debunk examples and lines of reasoning presented by some atheists (and other
skeptics) that are built around this logic. The first is the notion that it is impossible to prove negative. As the argument goes, it is inherently
hard to prove certain claims false as they are constructed in such a way that
they elude counterarguments. An often cited example was coined by Bertrand Russell in 1952: “If I were to suggest that between the Earth and Mars
there is a china teapot revolving about the sun in an elliptical orbit, nobody
would be able to disprove my assertion provided I were careful to add that the
teapot is too small to be revealed even by our most powerful telescopes.”
To break this argument down, consider the following scenario:
your five year old kid comes to you, waves his stuffed kangaroo in front of
your face and says: ‘Mommy, Timmy says he is hungry and wants you to put some
marshmallows in his pouch.’
This is a serious decision-making challenge that you are
facing now. Any bad decision can have negative consequences. If you do not give
Timmy marshmallows, and the claim made by your kid turns out to be true, the
poor creature could suffer or even starve, making your child desolate. However,
if the claim is false and you donate the marshmallows, they will surely end up
in the stomach of your little love, after spending some time in the dirty and
hairy interior of Timmy’s pouch. Similar decisions in long run can harm your
child’s health and erode your authority.
So what will you do? On one hand you have the child’s
testimony. On the other hand you have the following arguments:
- The claim is incompatible with scientific worldview. You could dissect Timmy and see inside that there is nothing that could generate human speech.
- The general experience is that stuffed animals do not talk. There are no verified examples (except when they are stuffed with electronics, but Timmy is not).
- The children at this age tend to make such things up. There is a lot of verified examples of children making claims that turned out to be untrue.
- The kid himself may have an interest in making you believe the claim. Certainly, he is projecting his own desires on Timmy, as marshmallows tend to be favorite food of kids, not stuffed kangaroos.
We know however from the previous section that this is
faulty reasoning leading to an irrational decision. You cannot evaluate kid’s
claim in isolation. You have to evaluate it together with the claim “he made it
up” and assign both claims probabilities. In the end, you will most likely
assign very high probability to the claim “he made it up” and act accordingly.
Maybe Timmy did speak and you may never be one hundred percent sure. But for
practical reasons, you have enough evidence to disprove it. The fact that you
cannot “positively” prove that Timmy did not speak is irrelevant.
This example is not as ludicrous as it sounds. It is indeed
very similar to the main topic of this essay. Note that supernatural religious
claims have similar characteristics:
- They cannot be explained using known and verified laws of nature.
- There are no verified examples of anything supernatural ever happening.
- People have a natural tendency to make up supernatural claims.
- People often have an interest in persuading you and a tendency to engage in intellectual gymnastics to make their arguments about supernatural look credible.
In fact, proving negative is very common and one does not
have to come up with fancy examples to show it. Proof by contradiction is a
valid logical way to prove non-existence of an object. In mathematics, a
well-defined object can be tested for consistency of its properties. If the
properties are inconsistent, the implication is that the object does not exist.
Similarly, an object in physics can have a well-defined and ever-present
influence on the environment. The lack of the influence implies that the object
does not exist.
Null hypothesis
I sometimes hear the notion of null hypothesis being brought
up in God debates, although the context is never clear enough for me to
formulate it. Nevertheless, it does not seem that the notion is used properly,
so let me explain what it is about. You can also read more on Wikipedia.
In statistics, a null hypothesis is a set of assumptions about
available data. Statisticians use the data to calculate certain value called test
statistic (example: sample average). If the assumptions of the null hypothesis
are satisfied, then it is mathematically proven that test statistic should have
a particular probability distribution. This means that the test statistic is
very likely to take on some values and less likely to take on other values
(example: your null hypothesis is that man are on average 6 feet tall; it implies
that your sample average is not likely to be around 7 feet). If the statistic
takes a value that is considered unlikely (your sample average turned out to be
7 feet), it indicates that you should reject the null hypothesis.
However, if your statistic takes on a likely value (your average
turns out to be 6.1 feet), it does not mean that you should accept the null
hypothesis. Virtually always, there exist multiple different null hypotheses that
could all be accepted. Sample size is never big enough to eliminate possibility
of unexpected random deviation (even though sample average is 6.1 it may turn
out that the true average among all men is 5.9 instead of 6 feet).
Null hypothesis is a tool for proving negative. It is very
similar to proof by contradiction. You start with some assumptions. If you end
up with a result that is unlikely, your assumptions are likely to be wrong. But
having a likely result does not prove the assumptions, because even with different
assumptions, you may end up with the same result just by chance.
Gumballs in a jar
Wikipedia contains the following example that explains
the burden-of-proof logic: there is a jar with gumballs. The number of gumballs
is either even or odd. There are two claims about reality:
- Number of gumballs is even.
- Number of gumballs is odd.
The failure of this example is in the fact that it is
irrelevant, because there is no decision involved. To fix it, we can add in a
decision problem. Let us say that you have to make a guess whether the number
is odd or even and if you make a wrong guess (or refuse to guess) you will be shot in the forehead with a Magnum.
Now the situation is quite different. In absolute absence of
information about the number of gumballs you will assign each claim a
probability of a half and pick at random. If on the other hand there is no
evidence except for somebody claiming that the number is even, you will not “disbelieve
this person by default until sufficient evidence is provided.” Instead, you
will choose “even” as your answer, unless you have reasons to believe that this
person may be misleading you.
Innocent until proven
guilty
Another popular example involves analogies to a court case.
In this scenario, a claim about the nature of reality is compared to a claim
that a person is guilty of murder. The burden of proof lies with the prosecutor
to prove the guilt, and judges (or jury, depending on the legal system) have to
produce a “guilty” or “not guilty” verdict (rather than “guilty” or “innocent”).
“Not guilty” in this case does not mean that the person was determined to be innocent.
It only means that there was insufficient evidence to ascertain guilt. In a similar
way, the burden of proof should lie with a person making a claim about the
nature of reality, and rejection of the claim does not automatically imply
acceptance of an alternative claim.
The argument that judges (jury) vote “guilty – not guilty”
is a word play. Recall that presumption of innocence is often phrased as
“innocent until proven guilty.” To keep the wording consistent with the
burden-of-proof logic, it should rather be phrased as “not guilty until proven
guilty.” But is it that these words have a deep significance to the logic of
the decision-making process? Or is it that they are based in tradition and do
not imply anything beyond their literal meaning?
In fact, a court decision is often a good example of how the
theory of decisions under uncertainty works. Both sides need to present their arguments.
There is both a prosecutor and a defense attorney who present different
accounts of the nature of reality. Based on their arguments, court assigns
probabilities to both stories. Then, within its legal constraints, court
considers costs and benefits of possible decisions it can make. Finally, a
ruling takes place.
The presumption of innocence indicates that courts ought to
be risk-averse in their rulings. That is, the probability of committing a crime
must be way above 50% for a person to be sentenced. This is a reflection of a
simple preference of our society: we consider sentencing an innocent person to be a greater injustice than letting a criminal get away with his crimes.
This is also valid from practical reasons: the information provided during a trial
is hardly ever complete and even judges are not perfectly rational, so we need
a great degree of certainty before we let them decide to ruin somebody’s life.
The reasons why decision-making process in courts is structured in such a way
are thus idiosyncratic. Using court rulings as a model for any decision is simply
wrong.
Evidence for claims
in science
‘Whenever scientists make a claim, they back it up with
evidence. You do not often see scientists making up unbacked theories’ another
argument goes.
That is true, a significant part of science is about
assessing which claims about reality are true and which are false. For example,
the framework of null hypothesis discussed above is a tool of science that
serves exactly that purpose. But still, there are reasons why this analogy is wrong.
The concept of a god is not something new that was recently invented
by a mad scientist. Theism is the incumbent idea. Similarly, geocentric model of
the Universe was the incumbent idea in the medieval times. Are you saying that
Copernicus could just have said ‘I do not accept geocentric model of the
Universe because it has not met its burden of proof’ and people should have
been persuaded? Incumbent ideas usually have some arguments backing them,
however flawed. If you want to dismantle an incumbent idea, you must provide
new arguments to counter the old ones.
But dismantling an incumbent idea is not enough. People need
information about the nature of reality in order to make decisions. If you
point out flaws in the only existing theory without providing an alternative
one, people have no choice but to still assign this theory probability 100%
when they are forced to make decisions. The only way to change that is to
introduce an alternative theory. And this new theory will require evidence.
The fact that science focuses so often on single claims rather
than decisions has a good reason: efficiency of communication. It is much
easier to discuss a single claim about the nature of reality than a decision
that entails multiple claims or a single claim in context of all decisions it
can be part of. Nevertheless, scientists often provide examples of decisions
their work can influence, to show why it is relevant. And new theories hardly
ever appear in vacuum. Virtually always, there is some sort of incumbent theory
which needs to be replaced. For example, the arguments supporting germ theory
were made to convince people whose previous theory was that disease was a
punishment from God. To use a familiar analogy: a scientist is like a prosecutor
or a defense attorney. It is not their job to make a decision; their job is to
provide evidence in favor of their account of the nature of reality.
Extraordinary claims
require extraordinary evidence
For people who believe in a god, it is often as self-evident
that their god exists, as it was self-evident to medieval astronomers that the
Sun revolved around the Earth. Imagine that you are one of those medieval
astronomers. Somebody comes up to you and says that your claim about the Sun
revolving around the Earth is extraordinary and you need to produce
extraordinary evidence for it, otherwise your claim is unbelievable. This
sounds ridiculous. Just look at the Sun.
It is all about perspective. Who decides what claims are
extraordinary and what type of evidence is required? Atheists may label theist
claims as “extraordinary” but they cannot just impose this labeling on theists
and expect them to accept it. If atheists want to have an actual dialog with
theists, they need to explain why theist claims should be labeled
“extraordinary.” This in turn entails providing and justifying and alternative
vision of reality, that is taking on the burden of proof.
There are many claims made by theists that can easily be
recognized as extraordinary even by the people who make them. The communication
failure happens, when the rule “extraordinary claims require extraordinary
evidence” is applied across the board without making sure that the other side
agrees with the labeling and with what labels imply.
The burden of proof
The decision to place the burden of proof on somebody who
claims existence is arbitrary. Theists often turn this argument on its head,
for example saying that we should then consider a claim that there exists a universe
without a god. The typical response from atheists is that it is a cop out. Is
it?
As I mentioned before, I consider only relevant questions. Both
existence and non-existence of a relevant object have their consequences (if
there are no consequences, then the object is irrelevant by definition). The
attempts to explain why we should prioritize one of these options over the
other are made only with examples of irrelevant objects, such as the celestial
teapot orbiting the Sun. To the contrary, people in general seem to be very
interested in establishing non-existence of relevant objects, especially if these
objects could threaten their wellbeing. Before walking into a gas chamber,
which of the following claims would you prefer to be proven: “Zyklon B is in
the chamber” or “there is no Zyklon B in the chamber?”
The notion of default position and the burden-of-proof logical
framework do not hold up when faced with practical problems. They are flawed
and must be discarded. But should we abandon the notion of burden of proof entirely?
Burden of proof can be understood as a communication device.
It can imply what the presuppositions are and who should provide the arguments
to counter these presuppositions, like in the case of judicial trial. In common
discussions, the burden of proof lays often with the person who wants to change
beliefs of other people. In general, the burden of proof is most often on the
person who challenges the incumbent idea. There is nothing wrong with it. But stating
that it should always be applied in this or any other way and making a rule of
logic out of it requires justification, not mere assertion.
Flying Spaghetti
Monster
Does it all mean that we have to debunk every possible
claim, no matter how ridiculous?
Let us consider the example of the Flying Spaghetti Monster
(FSM hereafter). Let us imagine that the question of existence of FSM is
relevant, that is our decisions should be based on the true nature of reality,
otherwise there is some sort of penalty: you will be sent to FSM’s hell if it
does exist and you do not observe prescribed rites or you will be wasting time
and being obnoxious if it does not exist and you do observe the rites.
Regardless of whether the decision process happens in your
head or whether it is held in a public forum, one of the arguments can be: “FSM
does not exist because it seems to be made up by some people in order to troll
other people.” An argument in favor of alternative point of view may be: “I had
a personal revelation from FSM that he exists.”
A person perceiving such an exchange has to consider both
arguments and assign probabilities to corresponding claims. How well a person
evaluates the probabilities depends on the qualities of the person, for example
how knowledgeable or intelligent she is. If a person comes to a conclusion that
the first of the arguments has no merit and the second one is all that is
needed, it just means that the person has either no clue how to evaluate
evidence or no knowledge about contemporary societies. The discussion with such
a person about the claim itself is thus pointless. Instead, this person
probably needs to be educated how to evaluate evidence in general, and such a
discussion is recommended instead.
On the other hand, a person who knows how to evaluate such arguments
will quickly conduct the entire reasoning in her head. It will happen in a
split second upon the first time she hears about the FSM. In fact, this happens
to most people. The results of this quick reasoning seem so obvious that people
often forget the reasoning even took place. So, yes, unfortunately every
ridiculous claim needs to be debunked. The good news is that it usually takes
less than the time needed to utter it.
Atheism
Atheism is most often defined as “a lack of belief in gods.”
Definitions often underline that it is not “a belief that gods don’t exist.”
The practical difference is that the latter definition includes only people who
thought about gods and concluded that they did not exist. The former
encompasses also people who have never thought about gods because this notion never
occurred to them as well as people who thought about gods but decline to provide
their stance.
Atheists often complain that people conflate these two
definitions. But the source of complaints is oftentimes not that individuals
got miscategorized, but because of the definitions’ supposed implications for
the burden of proof. In atheist worldview, the former definition shifts the
burden of proof to theists. The latter definition indicates that atheists are
making a positive claim which would require evidence and would place the burden
of proof on them. The question is: why people keep confusing the two
definitions?
A typical atheist neither goes to church nor observes other rituals
prescribed by religions. Most of the time, atheists know that if the claim
about God is correct, their wellbeing is in serious jeopardy. Nevertheless,
they keep on behaving as if gods did not exist. Yet they say that they are
atheists not because they think that gods do not exist. To the contrary, some
of them say that in addition to being atheists, they just happen to believe
that gods do not exist.
Consider a rational person deciding whether to go to church.
Under the theory of decisions under uncertainty, the person has to assign
probabilities to at least two claims and evaluate costs and benefits of the
decision under each possible version of reality. Such a person would not go to
church only if probability assigned to “God does not exist” is high. Yet some atheists say that they evaluate only the “God exists” claim. They do not assign
probability to the claim “God does not exist.” How is that possible? There are
a few possible explanations for this paradox:
- Atheism is a vapid notion that has no implications on the behavior of people under this label.
- Atheists are irrational in their decisions.
- Atheists are disingenuous by claiming that they do not hold a certain belief and yet they consistently behave as if they did.
- Theory of decision under uncertainty is wrong and cannot be applied to this situation.
Source of confusion
The entire essay could be probably replaced with a single
statement: “the claim that the default position and the burden-of-proof logical
frameworks are valid has not met its burden of proof; it should be thus
disbelieved by default.” However, as I am challenging an incumbent theory, I
feel obliged to provide as good arguments as possible. And arguing for the new
theory seems incomplete without speculating why the previous theory was so
readily accepted. I consider reasons to be the following:
- It is hard to realize that considering claims in isolation does not make sense. You need to conceptually link up claims with decisions and have a working model of decision making.
- A lot of intellectual activity focuses on claims, especially in science. It may seem natural to use claims as a basic unit and consider them in isolation.
- It is not in anybody’s interest to voluntarily give up an advantage. Putting the burden of proof on theists is convenient for atheists. Maybe this is why not enough effort has been made by atheists themselves to debunk the burden-of-proof logic.
- As Bertrand Russell pointed out, proving objectively non-existence is in some cases impossible, especially if the object in question is irrelevant (that is, it does not have a measurable influence on the people who argue about it). Given the recent tendency of theists to roll back their claims and to make them less and less relevant, it seems natural to demand more evidence supporting such claims.
- Some atheist feel like arguing against popular notion of God is similar to arguing against Flying Spaghetti Monster. The idea just seems to them so ridiculous that no arguments against it need to be made – on the contrary, strong arguments must be made to support such an “extraordinary” claim before it is even worth considering.
Consequences of
confusion
The last topic I would like to cover is why this is all
important.
First of all, using faulty logic is never good. The quality
of conclusions that can be drawn from a discussion at hand is not its only
victim. Invalid patterns of thinking once adopted by people, can be used in
other discussions as well. Therefore, it is not just the conclusions about gods
that are at stake, but the entire body of logic and all future conclusions that
could be reached for bad reasons.
Second reason is the easily observable failure of
communication between atheists and theists. Theists often have hard time trying
understanding the argument about burden of proof because it is so unintelligible.
The reason for it is not that theists lack intelligence, but that the argument
is wrong. As a result, it is much harder to reach an agreement. Theists are
left unconvinced that what atheists are saying makes sense and atheists are
frustrated that theists do not want to accept their arguments. Such an impasse
makes it easier to create hard feelings and makes it less easy to carry out
meaningful debate leading to a conclusion. In a nutshell, use of faulty logic
can impede propagation of good ideas.
Finally, holding on to the burden-of-proof framework is highly
counterproductive from the point of view of atheists themselves. Theists oftentimes
leave the discussion with a feeling that atheists are disingenuous. Almost all
atheists behave as if they believe that a god does not exist. Yet they keep on
saying that it is not their belief. This clear discrepancy between words and
actions is easily noticeable and many theists feel perplexed once exposed to
it. And they cannot be blamed, if in the end they conclude that atheists are
selling them bullshit.
Disclaimer
I use labels “atheists” and “theists” in the context of
media personalities who recently dominated public sphere, mostly YouTube, as
well as people who respond to these personalities. This essay does not intend
to objectively represent views of groups that use mentioned labels but rather
addresses some of the arguments made by some people in these groups.